We're not dead yet!
Tuesday, January 8, 2013
Monday, January 7, 2013
Reinventing the ecological wheel – why do we do it?
Are those who do not
learn from (ecological) history are doomed to repeat it?
A pervasive view within ecology is that discovery tends to
be inefficient and that ideas reappear as vogue pursuits again and again. For
example, the ecological implications of niche partitioning re-emerges as an
important topic in ecology every decade or so. Niche partitioning was well
represented in ecological literature of the 1960s and 1970s, which focused theoretical and experimental attention on how
communities were structured through resource partitioning. It
would be fair to say that the evolutionary causes and the ecological
consequences of communities structured by niche differences were one of the
most important concepts in community ecology during that time. Fast-forward 30
years, and biodiversity and ecosystem functioning (BEF) research slowly has come to the conclusion that niche
partitioning to explains the apparent relationship between species diversity and
ecosystem functioning. Some of the findings in the BEF literature could be criticized as simply being rediscoveries of classical theory and experimental evidence already in existence. How does
one interpret these cycles? Are they a failure of ecological progress or
evidence of the constancy of ecological mechanisms?
Ecology is such a young science that this process of
rediscovery seems particularly surprising. Most of the fundamental theory in
ecology arose during this early period: from the 1920s (Lotka, Volterra), 1930s (Gause) to 1960s (Wilson, MacArthur,
May, Lawton, etc). There are several reasons why this was the foundational
period for ecological theory – the science was undeveloped, so there was a void
that needed filling. Ecologists in those years were often been trained in other
disciplines that emphasized mathematical and scientific rigor, so the theory
that developed was in the best scientific tradition, with analytically resolved
equations meant to describe the behaviour of populations and communities. Most
of the paradigms we operate in today owe much to this
period, including an inordinate focus on predator-prey, competitive
interactions, and plant communities, and the use of Lotka-Volterra and consumer-resource models. So
when ecologists reinvent the wheel, is this
foundation of knowledge to blame, is it flawed or incomplete? Or does ecology fail
in education and practice in maintaining contact with the knowledge base that already
exists? (Spoiler alert – the answer is going to be both).
Modern ecologists face the unenviable task of prioritizing
and decoding an exponentially growing body of literature. Ecologists in the
1960s could realistically read all the literature pertaining to community
ecology during their PhD studies –something that is impossible today with an
exponentially growing literature. Classic papers can be harder to access than new ones: old papers are less likely to be accessible
online, and when they are, the quality of the documents is often poor. The
style and accessibility of some of these papers is also difficult for
readers used to the succinct and direct writing more common today. The cumulative
effect of all of this is that we read very little older literature and instead
find papers that are cited by our peers.
True, some fields may have grown or started apart from a
base of theory that would have been useful during their development. But it would
also be unfair to ignore the fact that ecology’s foundation is full of cracks. Certain
interactions are much better explored than others. Models of two species
interactions fill in for complex ecosystems. Lotka-Volterra and related
consumer-resource models make a number of potentially unrealistic assumptions,
and parameter space has often been incompletely explored. We seem to lack a
hierarchical framework or synthesis of what we do know (although a few people
have tried (Vellend 2010)). When models are explored in-depth, as Peter Abrams has done in many papers, we discover the complexity and possible futility
of ecological research: anything can result from complex dynamics. The cynic
then, would argue that models can predict anything (or worse, nothing). This is
unfair, since most modelling papers test hypotheses by manipulating a single
parameter associated with a likely mechanism, but it hints at the limits that current theory exhibits.
So the bleakest view of would be this: the body of knowledge that makes up ecology is inadequate and poorly
structured. There is little in the way of synthesis, and though we know many,
many mechanisms that can occur, we
have less understanding of those that are likely
to occur. Developing areas of ecology often have a tenuous connection to the
existing body of knowledge, and if they eventually connect with and contribute
to the central body, it is through an inefficient, repetitive process. For
example a number of papers have remarked that invasion biology has dissociated
itself from mainstream ecology, reinventing basic mechanisms. The most
optimistic view, is that when we discover similar mechanisms multiple times, we
gain increasing evidence for their importance. Further, each cycle of
rediscovery reinforces that there are a finite number of mechanisms that
structure ecological communities (maybe just a handful). When we use the same
sets of mechanisms to explain new patterns or processes, in some ways it is a
relief to realize that new findings fit logically with existing knowledge. For
example niche partitioning has long been used to explain co-occurrence, but
with a new focus on ecosystem functioning, it has leant itself as an
efficacious explanation. But the question remains, how much of what we do is
inefficient and repetitive, and how much is advancing our basic understanding
of the world?
By Caroline Tucker & Marc Cadotte
Wednesday, December 12, 2012
holiday caRd from the EEB & Flow 2012
To celebrate the start of the holiday season for many of us, the end of exams and marking for others, and for fellow Canadians, snow, enjoy this caRd from the EEB & flow! We will see you around the New Year with our traditional year-end post about the current state of ecology.
Or, copy and paste the code here into your R console.
Monday, November 19, 2012
Coexistence theory: community assembly's next great hope?
Rethinking Community Assembly through the Lens of Coexistence Theory
J. HilleRisLambers, P.B. Adler, W.S. Harpole, J.M. Levine, and M.M. Mayfield
The big (literally, at 24 pages) paper to read this year is a review by a number of well-known community ecologists that aims to package years of often contradictory and confusing results from community assembly research (Weiher & Keddy 2001) into a manageable package using coexistence theory. Coexistence theory arose particularly out of Peter Chesson’s work (particularly his own annual review paper (Chesson 2000)), and rests in the idea that coexistence between species is the result of a balance of stabilizing forces (i.e. niche differences) and equalizing forces (i.e. fitness similarity) between those species. Coexistence is stable when stabilizing forces dominate, so a species competes more strongly with itself than with other, more dissimilar, species. The most successful adaptations of this framework to “real world” experiments have come from Jonathan Levine’s lab (in collaboration with many of the coauthors on this work). Indeed, there are probably few people more qualified to attempt to re-explain the often complicated findings in community assembly research using coexistence theory.
The classic heuristic model for community assembly involves a regional species pool that is consecutively filtered through environmental and then biotic filters, selecting only for those species adapted to the local environment. While logically appealing, this model may have constrained thinking about assembly: after all, our definition of a niche recognizes that species are impacted by and impact their environments (Chase & Leibold 2003), and unlike a expectations for a biotic "filter", arrival order can alter the outcome of biotic interactions. But does coexistence theory do a better job of capturing these dynamics?
The important message to take from coexistence theory, the authors suggest, is that stabilizing niche differences facilitate coexistence, whereas relative fitness differences drive competitive exclusion. And although this yields predictions about how similar or different coexisting species should be, coexistence theory diverges in a number of ways from trait-based or phylogenetic approaches to community assembly. “First, competitive exclusion can either preferentially eliminate taxa that are too functionally similar when trait differences function as stabilizing niche differences or preferentially eliminate all taxa that do not possess the near optimal trait when such trait differences translate into fitness differences. Second, both stabilizing niche differences and relative fitness differences are influenced by abiotic and biotic factors. For both reasons, patterns of trait dissimilarity or similarity cannot easily be used to infer the relative importance of environmental versus biotic (competitive) filters, which is an important goal of community assembly studies.”
There are a number of ways in which pre-existing research might provide evidence for the predictions of coexistence theory. You can look at studies which modify fitness differences between species (for example, through nutrient addition experiments), those which modify niche differences (for example, manipulating colonization differences between species), and those which manipulate the types of species competing to establish. You can take advantage of trait or phylogenetic information about communities (and traits are valuable because they provide a mechanistic linkage), although Mayfield and Levine (2010) have already shown there are clear limitations to such approaches. A particularly useful approach may be to look at demographic rates, particularly looking for frequency-dependent growth rates, an indicator of niche differences between species – when niche differences are large, species should have higher growth rates at low density (lower intraspecific competition) than at high density. And indeed, there is some evidence for the effect of fitness differences or niche differences on community composition.
Ultimately reanalyzing old research has its limitations: is it possible that nutrient additions leading to changes in community structure are evidence of fitness differences? Yes. Are there other possible explanations? Yes. Convincing evidence will take new studies, and the authors make some excellent suggestions to this end: that we need to combine demographic and trait-based approaches so that assembly studies results suggest at mechanisms, not patterns. The focus would be on correlating niche and fitness differences with traits, rather than correlating traits with species’ presence or absence in the community.
Given the muddle that is community assembly research, a review that offers a new approach is always timely, and this one is very comprehensive and sure to be well cited. Strangely, for me this paper perhaps lacked the moment of insight I felt when I read about coexistence theory being applied to invasive species (MacDougall et al 2009) or phylogenetic analyses of communities (Mayfield and Levine, 2010). There are a few reasons why that might be: one is that there are difficulties that are not well explored, particularly that traits may not realistically be able to be categorized in an either-niche-or-fitness fashion, and that abiotic and biotic factors can interact with traits. The predictions this framework makes for community assembly are less clear: even the tidiness of coexistence theory can't escape the complications of community assembly. But perhaps that is a pessimistic take on community assembly. Regardless, the paper has a lot to offer researchers and will hopefully encourage new work exploring the role of niche and fitness differences in community assembly.
Tuesday, October 30, 2012
The contrasting effects of habitat area and heterogeneity on diversity
Sometimes I read a paper and Huxley’s famous quote seems
exceedingly appropriate. Why I say this is that a new idea or concept
is presented which seems both so simple and at the same time a potentially
powerful explanation of patterns in nature. This was my reaction to a recent paper from Omri Allouche and colleagues published in the Proceedings ofthe National Academy of Science. The paper presents a simple conceptual model,
in the same vein as Connell’s classic intermediate disturbance hypothesis,
which accounts for large-scale diversity patterns based on aspects of species
niche requirements as well as classic stochastic theory. Merging these two
aspects is a critical step forward, as in ecology, there has been a tension in
explaining diversity patterns between niche-based processes requiring that
species exhibit differences in their needs, and stochastic (or neutral)
explanations that ignore these differences, but seem to do well at large
scales.

Their heuristic prediction is that diversity is maximized at
intermediate levels of heterogeneity, as long as species have intermediate
niche breadths (i.e., they could perhaps use a couple of different habitats).
However, if their niche breadth is too narrow (i.e., they can only exist in a
single habitat type), then diversity may only decline with increasing
heterogeneity. Conversely, if species have very broad niche breadths (i.e., can
survive in many different habitats) then the tradeoff vanishes and
heterogeneity has little effect on diversity.
They tested this exceedingly simple prediction using
European bird data and found that species richness was maximized at intermediate
heterogeneity (measured by the variation in elevation). Further, when they
classified species into different niche width classes, they found that the
relationship between richness and heterogeneity changed was predicted (i.e.,
strongest for intermediate breadth).
This is a great paper and should have a large impact. It
will be exciting to see what other systems fit this pattern and how specific
studies later the interpretation or mechanisms in this model.
Allouche, O., Kalyuzhny, M., Moreno-Rueda, G., Pizarro, M., & Kadmon, R. (2012). Area-heterogeneity tradeoff and the diversity of ecological communities Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 109 (43), 17495-17500 DOI: 10.1073/pnas.1208652109
Allouche, O., Kalyuzhny, M., Moreno-Rueda, G., Pizarro, M., & Kadmon, R. (2012). Area-heterogeneity tradeoff and the diversity of ecological communities Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 109 (43), 17495-17500 DOI: 10.1073/pnas.1208652109
Friday, October 26, 2012
Open access: where to from here?
Undoubtedly, readers of this blog have: a) published in an open access (OA) journal; b) debated the merits of an OA journal; and/or c) received spam from shady, predatory OA journals (I know when my grad students have 'made it' when they tell me they got an e-mail invite to submit to the Open Journal of the Latest Research Keyword). Now that we have had OA journals operating for several years, it is a good time to ask about their meaningfulness for research and researchers. Bob O'Hara has recently published an excellent reflection on OA in the Guardian newspaper, and it deserves to be read and discussed. Find it here.
Thursday, October 18, 2012
Amusing titles for papers - the crowning touch?
I'll try for a more content-full blog post in the near future, but I couldn't help noticing that there are a number of papers in my reader this month with amusing titles. Titles are always one of the most difficult parts of writing a paper - how do you capture the important aspects of your paper in a minimum of words, while avoiding the usual traps of colons, question marks, and cliches (not to mention the urge to throw in buzzwords)? For that reason, I always appreciate authors willing to be a little intriguing, whether with metaphors, puns, or clever references.
(As an anecdote, I was in a reading group a week ago where we were discussing a paper about turtle movements. People couldn't stop making Ninja Turtle jokes throughout the meeting (academics are cool like that), and I'll admit I had a moment of jealousy over people who work with charismatic creatures which lend themselves to amusing references in papers and talks. There aren't too many jokes about computer models.)
Some amusing titles in the last month or two:
Taxonomy versus phylogeny: evolutionary history of marsh rabbits without hopping to conclusions
Declining woodland birds in North America: should we blame Bambi?
(As an anecdote, I was in a reading group a week ago where we were discussing a paper about turtle movements. People couldn't stop making Ninja Turtle jokes throughout the meeting (academics are cool like that), and I'll admit I had a moment of jealousy over people who work with charismatic creatures which lend themselves to amusing references in papers and talks. There aren't too many jokes about computer models.)
Some amusing titles in the last month or two:
Taxonomy versus phylogeny: evolutionary history of marsh rabbits without hopping to conclusions
Declining woodland birds in North America: should we blame Bambi?
Dragonflies: climate canaries for river management
Bayesian transmogrification of clade divergence dates: a critique

A slightly older but still excellent title:
The well-temperatured biologist
Although this study suggests that a clever titles will get cited less, I am at least more likely to read the abstract...
There are lots of classic titles I've overlooked, feel free to add them to the comments.
A slightly older but still excellent title:
The well-temperatured biologist
Although this study suggests that a clever titles will get cited less, I am at least more likely to read the abstract...
There are lots of classic titles I've overlooked, feel free to add them to the comments.
Friday, September 28, 2012
Scientific cul-de-sacs – fads in ecology
I’ve been thinking a lot about research topics I’m interested in pursuing once I finish (knock on wood) my PhD. During a conversation about possible post-PhD interests, a mentor warned me to be careful because they thought one topic might be a “fad”. I’m interpreting their definition of a “fad” as a subject that, while popular, is likely to be short-lived, misguided, and/or without a lasting impact. While we decided that the topic we were discussing is probably not a fad, it made me curious. How does one differentiates a faddish topic from a new but deserving idea or tool?
The scientific literature even includes a few papers about fads. And this is something they've been thinking about for a long time: in 1989 Warren G. Abrahamson, Thomas G. Whitham and Peter W. Price wrote a paper called “Fads in ecology” (in which they failed to identify any fads). Starbuck 2009 made excellent points about fads in the social sciences and behaviour that seem equally applicable to ecological research. Unfortunately, the first point these papers make is that identifying a fad is mostly about hindsight and even then, sometimes hindsight isn't enough. While Darwinism trumped Lamarckism in the 1800s, scientists now recognize that the idea of acquired characters is not (completely) wrong and ties into modern concepts like epigenetics. While most ecologists can think of some fads that have happened during their careers, picking a fad out in its early moments seems difficult. In the beginning, fads are simply attractive ideas, which slowly draw followers, until the number of people doing research on the topic reaches a critical mass. The way in which fads differ from a regular idea is that they rapidly establish, but this critical mass of research also rapidly makes the fad's limitations apparent. Once the promise of the fad is contradicted by evidence, people begin to jump ship.
It was also suggested to me that maybe fads shouldn't be judged too harshly, since they are just research bandwagon - topics which increase rapidly and disproportionately in attention, funding and publications. While some fads truly have negative effects on the science, most are simply overemphasized (hence their "faddish-ness") compared to other equally worthy topics, but still make contributions to science.
Ultimately we’re susceptible to fads because in a publish-or-perish academic setting such ideas often promise a great degree of generality or explanatory power and emphasize novelty. “These … fads may have occurred in part because researchers value novelty and they have limited tolerance for imitation” (Starbuck 2009). It's true that novelty carries risk, but it also can be very rewarding. The advice I received on choosing a research project has been divergent and sometimes contradictory - ranging from "avoid trending topics and fads by understanding the classic, proven work" (always good advice) to "feel free to join a bandwagon, but only if you're on the leading edge of it" (a little harder to follow). And perhaps that's the most interesting thing - successful academics seem to have taken many paths to success, suggesting that there is room to explore the scientific landscape a little.
Friday, September 14, 2012
In praise of Peter Abrams, at Dynamic Ecology
A nice tribute to Peter Abrams, an eminent ecologist and evolutionary biologist who is retiring this year, from Jeremy Fox at Dynamic Ecology. By virtue of being in the same department I've been lucky enough to interact with Peter and the experience is a highlight of my time there. All I'll say is that Peter is both humble and brilliant, and his work is both wide-ranging and very thorough. Most books on ecology or evolutionary biology include a long list of references to his work, and he's an essential part of our field.
Also, I'm sure the comments will have lots of nice anecdotes, so head on over.
Also, I'm sure the comments will have lots of nice anecdotes, so head on over.
Wednesday, August 22, 2012
Justifying assumptions: tests of seed size/mass tradeoffs
When ecologists develop theory and models, we
generally need to make assumptions. The nicest definition of an assumption is
that they are the framework we use to capture our beliefs about a system.
All future analyses will treat these assumptions as true, and so ultimately the
validity of a model is tied to the validity of its assumptions. As Joseph Connell said: “Ecological
theory does not establish or show anything about nature. It simply lays out the
consequences of certain assumptions. Only a study of nature itself can tell us
whether these assumptions and consequences are true.” Often times the most interesting advances in ecology come when we questions popular assumptions, such as that species are ecologically different, that interspecific differences are more important than intraspecific differences, or that ecological interactions occur much more rapidly then evolutionary changes.
Assumptions in models and theory can often serve as
a sort of shorthand for ideas that there is some general evidence for, but for
which comprehensive data may be lacking. Community ecology is
full of assumptions about functional tradeoffs that mediate coexistence between
species. Various assumptions about plant species coexistence include that
species experience tradeoffs between competition and colonization, growth
versus reproduction, or seed size versus seed number. A simplistic explanation
for such tradeoffs is that you can’t do everything well: a strong competitor
can’t be a good colonizer too, which creates opportunities for strong
colonizers but poor competitors, etc.
Tests of these functional tradeoffs are lacking, or lag behind the theory that relies on them. For example, the idea that there should be a tradeoff
between seed size and seed number has long been proposed to explain why plants
have highly variable seed sizes. Plants with small seeds should produce more
offspring, and these seeds should be more successful at reaching empty sites.
Large seeded species should be more competitive in the seedling stage or more
tolerant of difficult conditions, and so have higher survival. Theoretical models
that rely on such a tradeoff suggest that many species could co-exist and
that the resulting community would exhibit a wide variety of seed sizes.
But though many studies and theories depend on this
assumed tradeoff, a comprehensive experimental test was lacking. Ben-Hur et al. have finally provided such an experiment, testing the basic prediction that a negative
correlation between seed size and seed number should increase species richness.
They also tested whether small-seeded species were more likely to remain in the
community when this tradeoff existed, increasing the amount of among-species
variation in seed size. To do so, the authors created 3 ‘community
treatments’ of 15 plant species. The abundance of each species in the starting seed
mix was manipulated to create either (1) positive correlation between seed mass
and seed number; (2) negative correlation between seed mass and seed number or (3) random
allocation of the 15 species regardless of seed size.
Ben-Hur et al.’s results strongly suggest that a
seed size/seed mass functional tradeoff can increase species richness (figure, a). Further,
when there is such a tradeoff, the variation in seed size represented in a
community increases, again in agreement with predictions (figure, b). The results are
particularly convincing because the authors used experimental manipulation of
the strength of the correlation (i.e. from negative to positive) to test its
importance. The authors suggest that the
tradeoff they simulated did not involve competitive differences (i.e. was not a
competition-colonisation tradeoff), and more likely reflects a trade-off in
establishment probability and colonisation (Dalling and Hubbell 2002; Muller-Landau 2010).
Of course, these results represent relatively short-term coexistence, and community richness may have changed had the experiment been allowed to continue for longer. But as a starting point, this suggests that theories that rely on functional tradeoffs in seed characteristics to explain coexistence are capturing a mechanism that has some experimental support.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)